Aesthetic
Determinism: Contemporary Mytho-poeic Political Thought
William
Miller
wmiller711@gmail.com, wmiller@marymount.edu,
millerpolitics.com
Paper
presented to the Eric Voegelin Society at the 2024 APSA Conference in
Philadelphia.
I.
Introduction
Those
of us in the field of political philosophy or political theory are used to
discussing concepts and theories. I take a “concept” here to be simply a
definable, articulable idea and not a mere image: visual, auditory, or other.
Indeed, conceptual thinking in the practice of analysis, synthesis, and
evaluation of high order concepts and ideas is at the very heart of our study.
We
look at concepts to determine if they are sound; for example, whether an idea
that purports to be grounded in empirical reality can indeed be acceptably
verified. Or whether an idea that purports to be useful, is in fact coherent,
self-consistent, unambiguous, and non-tendentious: a good tool for discovering
elusive truth.
Plato’s classic
account of the “divided line” provides a most useful framework for
understanding the role of ideas in pursuing philosophic truth. You will recall
that the diagram he drew in speech—and perhaps in sand or on a wall in
Athens—is a four-part account of the content of human thought. Three horizontal
lines divided human thought into four kinds, ascending from the concrete to the
abstract: from ground level of the barest sensory images, or “sense
data” as I was once taught to call them, up through “things” that we can
identify, then through the concepts or hypotheses —from common nouns to
high order concepts—necessary for an act of identification and hypothetical
thinking, thence to the highest level of thought: the final realm of intuition
or pure thought. As analysts of
theory, we mill about on the third—and perhaps on the top—floor of that
four-story structure, evaluating the third-floor ideas that have variously been
translated as “hypotheses” or “graphic forms”.
Today,
my paper is about political thought, but not about the higher order conceptual
thought that analysts usually deal with. Rather, I am looking below Plato’s
second line into the thinking that takes place in what is usually referred to
as the lower two “visible” sections rather than the higher two “intelligible”
sections of the divided line image. The
essay “Myth and Reality” by the cultural anthropologists Henri and H.A.
Frankfort provides my point of departure. “Myth and Reality,” an introduction
to mytho-poeic thought, is the opening essay to the classic study of ancient
civilizations, The Intellectual Adventure of Ancient Man, still in print
after seventy-five years.[1]
Their essay cites Cassirer’s Philosophy of Symbolic Forms: Vol. II. Mythical
Thought as their only philosophic authority, and their account of mythical
thinking closely follows Cassirer’s analysis.[2]
We shall duly dig into Cassirer’s philosophy as well.
This
paper focuses on the myth-making process, both the making of myths and the
subsequent use of myth—the mytho-poeic consciousness or perspective, if you
will—not on the myths, ancient or modern, that have been produced. It is my
thesis—and I believe that Cassirer would largely agree—that for many if not for
most people today, the principal method of understanding and discussing
politics is still mytho-poeic thinking. And if this is true, it has significant
implications for contemporary politics and government, and politics and
government in all times.
II.
Principal Characteristics of Mytho-Poeic Thought
What
is “Myth”?
The
central thesis of the collection of essays by the Frankforts and others on the
ancient Egyptians, Mesopotamians, Hebrews, and Greeks in The Intellectual
Adventure of Ancient Man is that the ancients’ principal method of
understanding and of explaining to each other the world in which they lived was
mytho-poeic thinking. Cassirer’s theory of the symbolic form of mythical
thought supplies the philosophic foundation
“Myth”
here, of course, is not to be understood as the opposite of “fact,” as it is
commonly thought today, but as “story”—or, perhaps using the seemingly
ubiquitous term in current discourse, as “narrative;” either “story” or
“narrative” will do for us today. All myths are stories, that is to say, descriptions
of dramatic actions, but not all stories are “genuine” myths, those
produced by mytho-poeic thought. Nor are genuine myths simply another genre of
literature, like mysteries or historical fiction. As produced in ancient and in
contemporary primitive cultures, and perhaps even in today’s world, “genuine”
myths of the kind which the Frankforts and Cassirer also refer to as “true
myths” are fictional, but the fiction “is an unconscious, not a conscious,
fiction.”[3]
They [the myths of the ancients] are products of
imagination, but they are not mere fantasy. It is essential that true myth be
distinguished from legend, saga, fable, and fairy tale. All these may retain
elements of the myth. . . . But true myth presents its images and its imaginary
characters, not with the playfulness of fantasy, but with a compelling
authority. . . .
Myth, then, is to be taken seriously, because it
reveals a significant, if unverifiable, truth—we might say a metaphysical
truth.[4]
As
a fundamental mode of cognition, a fundamental means of understanding reality,
the myths created by genuine mytho-poeic thought always have reality as their
object. This distinguishes true myth from art or fantasy, which, according to
Kant, “is entirely indifferent to the existence or nonexistence of its object.”[5]
Nor
is the subject matter of true myth always easily categorized—as cosmogonies or
accounts of the actions of heroes and gods, for example. Mythical thinking can
interpret any object whatever.[6]
It is a particular mode of perception and conceptualization.
The
Frankforts’ “Myth and Reality”
From
the Frankforts’ “Myth and Reality,” we learn that mytho-poeic thought differs
from what we might call, begging a lot of questions, “rational” or “modern”
thought in several key ways. Ontologically, the ancients viewed the
world in a way fundamentally different from the modern, rational view we are
accustomed to:
For modern, scientific man the
phenomenal world is primarily an “It”; for ancient—and also for primitive—man
it is a “Thou.”[7]
This ontological
assumption attributes animal and human characteristics—sentience and
willfulness—to everything
in the natural world, and this consubstantiality encompasses nature as well as
the human or social world—society, tribe, clan—and sometimes even the tools man
makes.[8]
In
this environment of living beings, ancient man looks for causes by asking
“who,” not “how.” Thus, the rock trips man, man does not trip over the rock!
The rain broke the drought, not because of certain atmospheric and
meteorological conditions, but because
The gigantic bird Imdugud . . . came to their rescue.
It covered the sky with the black storm clouds of its wings and devoured the
Bull of Heaven, whose hot breath had scorched the crops.[9]
What
must be emphasized if we are to understand mytho-poeic thinking is that this
understanding of the world and its contents as a “Thou” and not as an “It” is
not the result of a two-step process of personification. The understanding or
apprehension of the world as “life” is immediate and irreducible. People who
think mytho-poeically do not first recognize a stone or tree or river as an
inanimate object and then consciously or reflexively refer to it and talk about
it as if it were animate with will and understanding. The stone, the
tree, the river are living, volitional beings: they are
experienced as living beings. As the Frankforts say:
This does not mean (as is so often thought) that
primitive man, in order to explain natural phenomena, imparts
human characteristics to an inanimate world. Primitive man simply does not know
an inanimate world. For this very reason he does not “personify” inanimate
phenomena nor does he fill an empty world with the ghosts of the dead, as
“animism” would have us believe. (Emphasis added.)[10]
I would hasten to add
that the animate beings that populate the ancient world are not necessarily
divine: not every rock and river is a god. After describing the mytho-poeic
ecology of ancient man, the Frankforts incidentally add the comment “the gods
also come into being in this manner.”[11]
Experiences of the sacred always presuppose recognition of the non-sacred—the
profane.[12]
Epistemologically, the characteristics of
mytho-poeic thinking as the mode of understanding the living beings who
populate the ancient world follow closely from this ontology. The Frankforts
emphasize that mytho-poeic thought is a mode of cognition, not mere fantasy or
wild imagination. It is the way we know, and, except for those who are still
recovering from their “Psychology 101” or “Introduction to Social Science”
course, it is the way we still know and talk about other human beings.
The
Frankforts distinguish among ways of knowing. To learn about things in the
world scientifically, we must be active, treating them as objects
and mentally and physically working on
them. We intellectually attempt to place particular objects within a framework
of general or universal rules and concepts and seek to identify them as instances
of a universal rule. To understand fellow creatures, we must in part remain passive,
holistically—that is, emotionally and intellectually—“understanding” the
creature facing us—“its fear, . . . its anger.” This “curiously direct
knowledge” of a fellow being is “direct, emotional, and inarticulate.”[13]
The
way of knowing “Thou,” whether a human being or a “personified” river, rock, or
mountain—and by “personified” here I mean the river, rock, or mountain
immediately apprehended as a living being—in the ancient cosmos, is closer to
the second mode of cognition than the first but not precisely the same. To know
someone else, we must be interactive with that living being: we must
actively probe and act, but we must also be passively open and receptive to
what the other being reveals to us. We find that each “Thou” with whom we
interact is unique, and each such experience is a unique event: the “relation
between ‘I’ and ‘Thou’ is absolutely sui generis.” Thou is known as
unique: not merely as an instance of universal laws: “Thou . . . is not merely
contemplated or understood but is experienced emotionally in a dynamic
reciprocal relationship.”[14]
In genuine mythical thought there is no hypothetical thinking, no critical
distance from the object, no application of norms or independent standards.
And
finally, both the understanding and articulation of that experience is
expressed in stories—descriptions of
dramatic actions:
All experience of “Thou” is highly individual; and
early man does, in fact, view happenings as individual events. An account
of such events and also their explanation can be conceived only as action and
necessarily takes the form of a story. In other words, the ancients
told myths instead of presenting an analysis or conclusions (emphasis added).[15]
The
“truth” of the experience is represented in these stories. As quoted above, “It
is essential that true myth be distinguished from legend, saga,
fable, and fairy tale.” Nor is true myth allegorical: it is not a story-line
conceived by an author and presented in imaginative fiction. It is spontaneous
expression of immediately experienced reality: it cannot be considered fable or
allegory, a product of an imaginative mind not tied to immediate reality. “In
telling such a myth, the ancients did not intend to provide entertainment.
Neither did they seek . . . intelligible explanations of the natural phenomena.
They were recounting events in which they were involved to the extent of their
very existence.”[16]
Main Points:
·
Mytho-poeic
thought presupposes a cosmos of life
·
The
apprehension of the world as life, as a Thou, is immediate, not intellectually
derived
·
Mytho-poeic
thinking is a mode of cognition, a means of knowing the world and of expressing
that knowledge, particularly appropriate to living beings
·
Mytho-poeic
cognition requires holistic—intellectual, emotional, and imaginative—
interaction with other living beings
·
Mytho-poeic
thought expresses those experiences of the living world as stories,
descriptions of dramatic interactions
I
chose this essay by contemporary cultural anthropologists as my point of
departure because they present the main characteristics of mythopoeic thinking
in the context of an actual study of particular ancient cultures.[17]
The philosopher Ernst Cassirer provides the philosophical and psychological
foundation for understanding how mytho-poeic thinking functions in general.
Ernst
Cassirer’s Symbolic Forms
Cassirer
(1874-1945) was engaged in formulating a “philosophy of human culture.”[18]
He understood human culture to be the totality of the expressions of our
experience of the world without and within. His original title for his
three-volume work, The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, was “the theory of
the forms of spiritual expression,” “spiritual” referring here to the human
spirit, the mental, emotional, and intelligent element of our actions which
accounts for the ways we articulate our experiences. Cassirer argues that human
beings express our experiences by objectifying them using “symbols” taken from
the world around us. Symbolic objectification distinguishes us from the
animals.[19]
He adduces a number of forms of spiritual expression or “symbolic forms:” myth,
religion, language, art, history, poetry, law, and science or “pure knowledge,”
to name just a few.
I
am not going to review all of the symbolic forms—Cassirer studies language,
myth, and science in the first three volumes of PSF—but two of them,
myth and language, are essential to our topic and are also, he says, the most
primitive and fundamental modes of expression.[20]
Though the first volume of PSF focuses on language, this initial
discussion does not mean that Cassirer thought the development of language
preceded the development of myth.
Language and myth stand in an
original and indissoluble correlation with one another, from which they both
emerge but gradually as independent elements. They are two diverse shoots from
the same parent stem, the same impulse of symbolic formulation, springing from
the same basic mental activity, a concentration and heightening of simple
sensory experience. . . . they are both resolutions of an inner tension, the
representation of subjective impulses and excitations in definite objective
forms and figures.[21]
Thus,
Cassirer’s discussion necessarily extends beyond the Frankforts, whose focus
was only on the ancient but fully-developed cultures of Mesopotamia, Egypt, and
the Hebrews, all of which existed long after language and myths first
developed. These cultures already represent considerable progress in the forms
of language and mythmaking. They also represent generations of
tradition—teaching, conditioning, passing on, and amending the stories,
language, and knowledge rooted in earlier mytho-poeic thought.
I do not want to go too deeply into the
actual psychological process of language making and ritual-myth myth that
Cassirer analyzes at length in his early works.[22]
Cassirer explains that myth-making, like speech, is a means of expressing our
emotional, not our purely intellectual or rational, reaction to phenomena.[23] Rituals certainly have definite behavioral
structures, and myth has its roots in rites. Myths or stories also have an
intellectual structure to them, provided by language. Though it would appear,
then, that myth-making follows upon the development of language, they are
shoots, as Cassirer says above, “from the same parent stem, the same impulse of
symbolic formulation.” They develop symbiotically over time; the question of
which came first, he says, is “specious.”[24]
The roots of myth go deeper into the basic, animal,
emotional reactions to phenomena that do not require language: they are
expressed by animals and men in spontaneous reactions, physiological or
physiognomic, and manifested emotionally.
Every organism ‘seeks’ certain
things and ‘avoids’ certain things. . . . All this is regulated by a complicated
network of instincts and motor impulses which do not require conscious
activity (emphasis added).[25]
The objectification of these spontaneous
emotions begins in rituals: structured physical, non-linguistic,
behaviors associated with or triggered by certain recurring stimuli. In other
words, they precede language and therefore precede myth as spoken story.[26]
They are also intensely social, not individual. In taking one’s part in ritual,
the individuality of the participant is lost, traded for solidarity with the
group.[27]
Myths describes rituals.[28]
This, I believe, is the central fact about myth that needs the most emphasis: rituals and genuine myths are expressions of
man’s emotional responses to their experience, which are themselves the product
of physiologic or physiognomic reactions.[29]
“Here we grasp one of the most
essential elements of myth. Myth does not arise solely from intellectual
[spiritual] processes; it sprouts forth from deep human emotions. . . . Myth
cannot be described as bare emotion because it is the expression of
emotion. The expression of a feeling is not the feeling itself—it is emotion
turned into an image. . . . what hitherto was dimly and vaguely felt assumes a
definite shape . . . .”[30]
“[I]n myth man begins to learn a
new and strange art: the art of expressing, and that means organizing, his most
deeply rooted instincts, his hopes and fears.”[31]
Cassirer
also emphasizes that myths and words express collective, social feelings,
not the unique feelings of individual human beings. The symbols used to
objectify the sensory stimuli, both in the formulation of names and myths,
understandably reflect the conditions in which primitive man lived—weather,
geography, and particularly social order were prominent sources of symbols.
Symbolic objectification is part of man’s process—the human task, he calls
it—of differentiating “things” from the flow and flux of sensory stimuli that
language-less primitive man, and babies everywhere, experience. The familiar
environmental and social conditions thus provide the connectedness or the
“logic” of the ancient cosmos. The natural world is fundamentally conceived as
a social environment. The cosmos and the gods reflect the order of
primitive society and vice versa. In the Frankforts’ Intellectual Adventure
of Ancient Man, these “cosmological societies” are exemplified by the
cultures of ancient Egypt and Mesopotamia.[32]
Recalling
the consubstantiality or “consanguinity,” as Cassirer calls it, of the cosmos
of life in which primitive man lives, we can understand that “myth is an
objectification of man’s social experience, not his individual experience,”
which early on still required differentiation from the group.[33]
Languages and stories are means of communication: their formulation requires
the cooperation and coordination of the group. In ancient times, the
thirty-five members of the tribe did not operate with thirty-five different
languages or thirty-five different mythical accounts of reality.
Main points:
·
Mytho-poeic
thinking is the human expression of our emotional reaction to phenomena.
·
Rituals
and myths are the objectivizations of those emotional experiences.
·
Mytho-poeic
thought is irreducible because emotional and physiognomic reactions are our
“lowest stratum of sense experience,” lower even than sense perception[34]
·
Myths
reflect their creators’ social conditions: they are social, not individual,
creations
·
Rituals
seek social, emotional solidarity
Thus, in terms of Plato’s divided
line, mythical expressions—mythical symbolic forms—and language precede the
recognition and identification of objects represented by Plato as the second
level from the bottom. Because it precedes or is more fundamental than
conceptual thought, myth cannot be reduced to another distinct conceptual
(“rational”) foundation, which foundation does not yet exist. Mytho-poeic
thinking is inherent in human life.
The Appeal of
Stories
A
vital step in the search for mytho-poeic thinking in modern times is the
attraction and appeal of stories in our world and throughout history. Though
Cassirer does not directly address this question, I believe that recent
research into the appeal of stories fits into his theory of the unconscious
reactions animals have to certain external stimuli. Referring back to his
comments on the “protoplasmic” flight-or-fight instincts of all living
creatures, it appears that the appeal of stories also arises from “a
complicated network of instincts and motor impulses which do not require
conscious activity.”[35]
According to Cassirer,
human culture is the sum total of all of the symbols expressing/articulating
our experience of the world without and within. Mythical or mytho-poeic
thinking is at the foundation of human culture.
Western culture and all
the other cultures that I have studied in my lifetime are permeated with
stories, some the primeval expressions of emotional reactions, but the bulk
consciously created in more recent times to entertain, inform, and to simply
articulate and convey to others. Stories (Geschichte) presented in
epics, legends, scripture, and stories presented in the form of literature,
movies, history (Geschichte), and fiction are essential for
communication with one another on all but the most basic animal level. But
there is the undeniable natural appeal of stories, as well. People—not all
people, of course—get caught up in a story. Those who cannot are often called
“unimaginative,” not a compliment. Think of the Homeric bards reciting the
epics; then the millions captivated and enthralled by Harry Potter or Luke
Skywalker.[36]
In recent years, this
common-sense observation has been supported by hard science. MRIs reveal that
listening to stories “light up” different areas of the brain, networks
associated with language and “other neural networks, too.” “[Y]our brain waves
actually start to synchronize with those of the storyteller.”[37]
“[M]otor and sensory cortices, as well as the frontal
cortex are all engaged during story creation and processing. These networks are
nurtured and solidified by feelings of anticipation of the story’s resolution,
involving the input of your brain’s form of candy, dopamine.”[38]
And that’s not the only biochemical reaction: storytelling triggers “dopamine,
cortisol, oxytocin, and endorphins,” says Philipp Humm.[39]
Oxytocin seems particularly significant: “[W]hen we hear a story that resonates
with us, our levels of a hormone called oxytocin increase.”[40]
These recent findings have not been lost on the
business community—where salesmen
lead, can politicians be far behind?[41]
Nor on those with broader perspectives:
“The
scary thing is that stories are actually very effective ways to spread
misinformation,” said [Reyhaneh] Maktoufi. Plus, some of the best conspiracy
theories and propaganda employ skilled narrative techniques. “When you're
really transported in a story, you're less likely to actually spot lies and
falsehoods.”[42]
III. Age of Ideological
Scenarios
Because “stories” or
myths are today more an art form than the description of ritual or an
expression of raw emotional reaction expressed in “genuine” or “true” myth, I
have borrowed the artistic or aesthetic sense of “story” for my title
“aesthetic” determinism. The aesthetic imperative is “to do what the story
requires” or “to perform one’s role”
or “to follow the script.” I have assumed or stipulated that all myths are
stories, but that not all stories are myths, though the borderline between the
two is not always easy to determine. When people act pursuant to an aesthetic
imperative or cosmic screenplay, then morality, law, and even self-preservation
are subordinated to doing what one must do according to the story or the myth.
The emphasis on acting also suggest the element of ritual.
The most recent period in which aesthetic determinism
was a major factor in political action was the first half of the Twentieth
century, with roots in the latter half of the Nineteenth, when millions were
enthralled by the cosmic scenarios of communist and Nazi ideology, what Karl
Popper referred to “historicism,” plays “performed on the Historical Stage.”[43]
Communism, of
course, was but another millenarian fantasy rooted in Revelation chapter
20. The orthodox version of Marxism laid out a historical roadmap for
communists to follow. The story was eschatological, a “teleological critique”
in Professor Niemeyer’s terminology.[44]
Nazism was not a teleological ideology of the
millenarian type. It rather projected an allegedly biological order upon
reality assigning all human beings to their place on the chart: people were to
behave according to their racial identity. Nazism was an “axiological
critique.”
In both cases, many members of the ideological party
no-doubt acted out of individual self-interest or lust-for-power.[45]
But the symbols prominent in both movements were cosmic scenarios proclaiming
the inevitability of future victory for the followers of the screenplay. The
stories that were the foundation of the movements enabled the followers to
understand and to explain the course of world affairs to themselves and others
and to meaningfully struggle to achieve the end—la fine. They were both
attempts to create cosmological societies.
Cassirer’s The Myth of the State, written
during World War II, is an analysis of what he calls “the myth of the twentieth
century:” the Nazi racial ideology.[46] He
makes no mention of communism. After his excellent opening chapters summarizing
and expanding upon his earlier discussions of “genuine myth” in PSF and Language
and Myth, he provides a substantive history of the “legal state,” a
discussion of the “philosophical” influences on the Nazi theorists—Carlyle and
the hero myth, Gobineau and the racial myth, and Hegel and the nationalism
myth—and two final hortatory chapters on preventing a recurrence of the
totalitarian myths in the future.
He begins his book with the statement, “The
preponderance of mythical thought over rational thought in some of our modern
political systems is obvious.” And he
concludes with the statements that myth “is always there, lurking in the dark
and waiting for its hour and opportunity,” and:
“The powers of myth were
[historically] checked and subdued by superior [cultural] forces. As long as
these forces, intellectual, ethical, and artistic, are in full strength, myth
is tamed and subdued. But once they begin to lose their strength chaos is come
again. Mythical thought then starts to rise anew and to pervade the whole of
man’s cultural and social life. . . .”[47]
What he does not do is demonstrate systematically how
the myth-making process so carefully laid out in the first part of the text
relates to the contemporary myths, or totalitarian ideologies as we might call
them, that he studies in the book. Indeed, he concedes, as he must, that the
“new political myths . . . are artificial things fabricated by very skilful (sic) and cunning artisans. Henceforth, he says,
myths can be manufactured in the same sense and according to the same methods
as any other modern weapon—as machine guns or airplanes.[48]
We are left with an analytical focus
upon the receivers, the consumers, of the myths, not the creators. “In
desperate situations man will always have recourse to desperate means—and our
present-day [1940s] political myths have been such desperate means.” “In
periods of relative stability and security, this rational organization [of
society] is easily maintained.” But in critical times, such as post WWI
Germany, even intelligent and well-educated individuals despair of rational
solutions and are open to and reach for irrational, mythical salvation.[49] He
vigorously warns of the consequences of such a choice—the elimination of
individual responsibility, the relapse from critical thinking into complete
acquiescence, the transvaluation of ethical values, and the transformation of
language.[50]
The focus of his study changes from myth-making to myth-following over the
course of his discussion of “political myths.”
In sum, Cassirer offers one of the
earliest analyses of the modern, malignant ideologies that are based on cosmic
screenplays.[51]
He is greatly concerned about the reappearance of totalitarian movements in the
future, but apart from his wise, heartfelt warning, he offers but few comments
about the appearance of mytho-poeic thought in other contexts.
The imminent threat of totalitarian movements based
upon cosmic scenarios seems over for the moment, at least in the Western
democracies. Certainly at home and in the world beyond, there are a few
holdover millennialist and totalitarian movements that boast significant
followings: ISIS and Shi’ite apocalypticism and a few environmental groups come
to mind.[52]
According to Kenneth Minogue’s analysis, in Western society the cosmological
ideologues gave up their grand schemes—or at least temporarily stashed aside
their characteristic millenarian symbols—in favor of a new, non-imagic symbol to motivate their followers—“ethics.” In
light of the glaring failures of the Marxist and Marxist-clone movements to
realize the earlier telos or denouement, ideologies based upon
the fundamental and necessary Gnostic assumption that we live in an evil,
oppressive world, says Minogue, now support a struggle for an “ethical” world:
“a seductive invitation to join a movement bent on creating the better world to
which all reforms must point.”[53]
But the new program at this time does not have the
clarity of plot and character that the older scenarios provided and that a good
story needs to captivate the masses. “ ‘Do this’ and ‘do that’ because it will
make the world a better place” lacks the clear concreteness that myths, both
primeval and conscious, possess. The motivation arises from an argument, not a
story, not a description of actions. Where then does the emotion-driven
participant in politics—particularly in the politics of Western democratic
nations—exercise qualities of mytho-poeic thinking today?
IV. Contemporary
Mytho-poeic Thinking.
Though as a society, we do not appear to be in the
throes of a crisis of the magnitude that, according to Cassirer, sent Germany
into Nazism, there is evidence of mytho-poeic thought or consciousness, both
political and non-political, in contemporary life. I am not arguing that we
are witnessing or are part of a period of time in which genuine myths,
as described by Cassirer and the Frankforts, are being created or followed by
masses of people throughout the world. Indeed, Cassirer conceded that modern
political myths are “artificial things fabricated by very skilful
(sic) and cunning artisans.” Where do we find the qualities of genuine myth
today?
I will take from Cassirer’s analysis his focus on the
consumers, not the creators, of myth. The susceptibility to and acceptance of
myths by people throughout the ages indicate that a significant characteristic
of mytho-poeic thinking is now, and always was, a particular mytho-poeic social
consciousness, or perhaps, “attitude,” that permitted and encouraged, not to
say “forced,” people to accept the stories as reality: “forced” because to
ancient man mytho-poeic reality was the only known reality, and it was
maintained and taught by the culture. Today, modern “rational” thought is
dominant, though not exclusive. My question is, “What leads people today to suspend disbelief and to submit to the
aesthetic imperatives?” The physiological attraction of stories and the
fundamental impulse—not free predilection—to respond emotionally rather than
critically to the human activities of politics and government, puts the focus
on the followers, not the leaders, in politics. Thus, to find mytho-poeic
thinking at work in contemporary society, we must focus on the attitude and
perspective of the followers not the creators of myth.
What characterizes
mytho-poeic responses? Keeping in mind Cassirer’s observation that myth “is not
always operative in the same way nor does it always appear with the same
strength,” I suggest the following characteristics reflect the mytho-poeic
consciousness. First, is an intense concern for life, for people, a
reference to the environment full of life that confronted primitive man.
Second, an immediate, irreducible, emotional response to phenomena.
Third, a desire to lose one’s individuality, including one’s independent
judgement and critical distance, by ritualistic immersion in society, in
the crowd. Fourth, a discourse that comfortably focuses on and largely consists
of descriptions of dramatic—human—action; in other words, stories and
story-telling.
Let’s
first look at mytho-poeic thinking generally, not just politically. Cassirer
reminds us: “[E]ven in the life of the civilized man
[myth] has by no means lost its original power. If we are under the strain of a
violent emotion we have still this dramatic conception of all things.”[54]
Personally,
I have had frequent dramatic conversations with my computer, my printer, and my
car while “under the strain of a violent emotion.” Perhaps you have, too.
Thinking as “phenomenologically” as I can, I cannot discern two steps in these
conversations: “Step One: This is an electronic machine, but, Step Two: I am
going to treat it now as if were a living being with a will of its own.” No,
the emotional and the perceptual reaction that I immediately had was that I was
in the presence of a living being—an evil living being—with malice
aforethought. An irreducible emotional reaction to a living being.
A
casual conversation at a family gathering twenty-plus years ago may also be
relevant. I was speaking with an intelligent individual who was employed in a
responsible, management position. When we were discussing mutual acquaintances,
colleagues, and family members, their actions and feelings, what they said and
did not say, what they should have or should not have done, she was relaxed and
talkative. When the subjects of our conversation became just a bit more
abstract and speculative than what was essentially gossip, her manner markedly
changed. She became visibly uncomfortable when I asked about what might be
called “policies” or “ideas”—nothing political, derogatory, or remotely
confidential—until we returned to the subject of people. I have since noticed
this with other educated, intelligent people, even old friends. Their interests
are on concrete, personal, “sub-conceptual” subjects, best discussed through
stories requiring the little critical or speculative judgment, and not on
“topics” or “issues.” I think both of
these individual non-political behaviors reflect elements of mythopoeic
consciousness.
I
would also recall the earlier statements about the attraction and effect of
story-telling and would add the common experience of melting emotionally and
un-consciously into the crowd at games and concerts, especially exciting games
and concerts. It feels good, especially if we win. All four of these examples
emphasize the emotional, sub-conceptual consciousness of Plato’s first level of
thought.
Turning
to politics, it seems that the subject of politics in general immediately
satisfies the criteria. Politics is about people, and while it should also be
about reasonable policies, the current political atmosphere seems dominated by
“personalities, not policies;” but that perspective is always present in some
degree. The behavior that first suggested to me the presence of mytho-poeic
thought in recent times is the intense emotional fervor present in many
contemporary elections: the passionate rhetoric; the hate of our opponent, more
than the love of our champion; the desire for explanation of salient issues by
story or narrative rather than by rational argument.
The
populist, up-from-the-bottom, influence of today’s American politics can be
expected to inject emotional enthusiasm into our political dialogue; the
frequent periods of populist politics in the past would so indicate. But
populism derives much of its force from the concrete, material interests of its
movers; the emotion of present politics lacks those identifiable, tangible
interests.
The
problems with mytho-poeic political thinking in today’s world? The experience
of concrete interaction with politicians is all but impossible at the level of
national politics. The interaction needed to know someone has been supplanted
by interaction with an image, with a carefully constructed persona “known” via
electronic media. Or, known at rallies and mass events where the politicians
perform or interact with the “crowd,” not with individuals.
The
preference for stories or narratives rather than rational explanations of any
degree of complexity is also a problem. Like any drama, there is a focus on
plot and characters: a primary focus on human action, on what people do, don’t
do, should do; and with it a focus on human characters, on whether the human
subjects are appealing or repulsive? In other words, the stuff of gossip.
Attempting to understand complex subjects through narratives alone also
encourages the acceptance of and use of tales of conspiracy. Politics has the
raw materials for a “dramatic conception,” factual and fictional.
The
natural, emotional response to drama is also hazardous. As we saw with the
research on story-telling, knowledge of the mechanisms of human reaction
encourages manipulation of those mechanisms. Political campaigns have become
filibusters of accusations and stories calculated to excite and stir up
emotions. The intricacies of policy not only are lost: they are even hard to
find.[55]
I
am not arguing that the appearance of this mytho-poeic attitude is a recent
phenomenon, emerging first in the early twentieth century and perhaps enjoying
a resurgence now. The politics of the post-Civil War years was characterized by
robust partisanship and intense emotions.[56] Selecting
candidates that “appeal” to the voters, trying to excite the voters, stirring
up and motivating your base, these practices are and long have been a normal
part of democratic politics. But our national politics have not always been so
raucous, at least during my lifetime.
Cassirer
said, myth, and we might add, the mythical consciousness, “is always there,”
and he urged reasoned, critical thinking in political discourse. Reason, as
Hobbes famously said, “is not, as sense and memory, born with us, nor gotten by
experience only, as prudence is, but attained by industry.”[57]
We’ve got to work at it. We must cultivate our critical judgment and do our
best to rationally govern the emotions arising from our spirit and our
appetites below. “As long as these forces, intellectual, ethical, and artistic,
are in full strength, myth is tamed and subdued. But once they begin to lose
their strength chaos is come again.”[58]
Select Bibliography
Ernst Cassirer. An
Essay on Man. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1944.
________ . Language and
Myth, translated by Suzanne K Langer. New York: Dover Books, 1946. First
published in 1924.
________. “Language and
Art I” and “Language and Art II.” In Symbol, Myth, and Culture: Essays and
Lectures of Ernst Cassirer, 1935-1945, edited by Donald Phillip Verene,
145-195. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1979.
________. The Logic of
the Humanities, translated by Clarence Smith Howe. New Haven: Yale
University Press, 1960, 1961. Originally published 1942. Available on Internet
Archive.___
________. The Myth of the
State. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1946.
________. The Philosophy of
Symbolic Forms: Mythical Thought, translated by Ralph Manheim. New Haven:
Yale University Press, 1955. Volume 2 of the three, now four, volume work on The
Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, it was first published in 1925.
________. “Mythic,
Aesthetic, and Theoretical Space.” In The Warburg Years (1919-1933): Essays
on Language, Art, Myth, and Technology. New Haven: Yale University Press,
2013. Chapter first published in 1931. Stable URL—https:
//www.jstor.org/stable/j.ctt5vm3n3.12.
________. Symbol, Myth,
and Culture: Essays and Lectures of Ernst Cassirer, 1935-1945. Ed. Donald
Phillip Verene. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1979.
Cabañas, Kaira M. “Physiognomic
Gestalt.” In Learning from Madness. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 2018.
Eliade, Mircea. The
Sacred and the Profane. New York: Harper and Row, 1961.
________
Frankfort, Henri, et al. The
Intellectual Adventure of Ancient Man. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1946.
Katsur, Ira Irit. “Gestalt
Psychology as a Missing Link in Ernst Cassirer’s Mythical Symbolic Form.” Human
Studies 41 (Spring 2018): 41-57. Stable URL—https:
//www.jstor.org/stable/44979877.
O’Connor, Edwin. The Last Hurrah.
Boston: Little, Brown, and Co., 1956.
Pedersen, Esther Oluffa. “The Holy
as an Epistemic Category and a Political Tool: Ernst Cassirer’s and Rudolph
Otto’s Philosophies of Myth and Religion.” New German Critique 104. Vol
35, No 2. (Summer 2008): 207-227.
Prior, Marcus. “News vs.
Entertainment: How Increasing Media Choice Widens Gaps in Political Knowledge
and Turnout.” American Journal of Political Science 49 (July 2005):
577-592.
Zweig, Jason. “How to Stay Sane
When the Market Goes Wild.” Wall Street Journal. August 10-11, 2024,
sec. B1, p. 1.
On Stories and Storytelling
“Storytelling And
The Brain: Understanding The Neuroscience Behind Our Love For Stories,” Philipp
Humm, Power of Storytelling.com (February 7, 2023)
Our love for
storytelling is deeply rooted in our brain and its unique structure and
function. By triggering dopamine, cortisol, oxytocin,
and endorphins, you can capture your audience’s attention, evoke
empathy, and make them feel good.
“The Science of
Storytelling: Why We Love Stories,” by Joshua VanDeBrake, published in The
Startup and on <medium.com> (September 27, 2018).
You have likely
heard that storytelling is important for business, marketing, and
for life in general. Likely, you’ve heard that it’s a powerful tool and that it
has a potential for massive lasting impact.
There is a scientific
explanation for our love of stories: when we hear a story that resonates
with us, our levels of a hormone called oxytocin increase.
“How Stories
Connect And Persuade Us: Unleashing The Brain Power Of Narrative,” By Elena
Renken, npr.org (April 11, 2020)
On functional MRI
scans, many different areas of the brain light up when someone is listening to
a narrative, Neeley says — not only the networks involved in language
processing, but other neural circuits, too. One study of
listeners found that the brain networks that process emotions arising from
sounds — along with areas involved in movement — were activated, especially
during the emotional parts of the story.
As you hear a
story unfold, your brain waves actually start to synchronize with those
of the storyteller, says Uri Hasson, professor of psychology and neuroscience
at Princeton University.
“The Neuroscience
of Storytelling,” by NLI Staff, The NeuroLeadership Institute (September 30,
2021)
When we see or
hear a story, the neurons in our brain fire in the same patterns as the
speaker’s, a process known as “neural coupling.” You also hear it referred to
as “mirroring.” According to highly-cited work by Greg J. Stephens, Lauren J.
Silbert, and Uri Hasson, these processes occur across many different areas of
the brain, and can induce a shared contextual model of the situation. The
motor and sensory cortices, as well as the frontal cortex are all engaged
during story creation and processing. These networks are nurtured and
solidified by feelings of anticipation of the story’s resolution, involving the
input of your brain’s form of candy, dopamine.
That’s why when we
experience an emotionally-charged event or hear a story of the same nature,
certain parts of our brain release excess dopamine, making it easier to
remember something with greater accuracy.
“Why Your Brain
Loves Good Storytelling,” by Paul J. Zak, Harvard Business Review (October 28,
2014)
In subsequent
studies we have been able to deepen our understanding of why stories
motivate voluntary cooperation. (This research was given a boost when,
with funding from the U.S. Department of Defense, we developed ways to measure
oxytocin release noninvasively at up to one thousand times per second.)
We discovered that, in order to motivate a desire to help others, a story must
first sustain attention – a scarce resource in the brain – by developing
tension during the narrative. If the story is able to create that tension then
it is likely that attentive viewers/listeners will come to share the emotions
of the characters in it, and after it ends, likely to continue mimicking the
feelings and behaviors of those characters. This explains the feeling of dominance
you have after James Bond saves the world, and your motivation to work out
after watching the Spartans fight in 300.
These findings on
the neurobiology of storytelling are relevant to business
settings.
“Why the Brain
Loves Stories,” by Calli McMurray, BrainFacts.org (March 4, 2021)
The brain is a
story addict, always on the hunt for a character. If you’ve listened to hours
of podcast episodes or stayed up until 3 a.m. binge-watching a TV series, you
know the power of good narrative.
“The
scary thing is that stories are actually very effective ways to spread
misinformation,” said [Reyhaneh] Maktoufi, [a Civic Science Fellow in
misinformation at NOVA]. Plus, some of the best conspiracy theories and
propaganda employ skilled narrative techniques. “When you're really
transported in a story, you're less likely to actually spot lies and
falsehoods.”
“The Big Question:
Why Do We Tell Stories?” by The New York Times (December 8, 2022)
Christopher
Wheeldon: ‘The Tormented Tempest of the Human Condition’
We tell stories
because it’s easier to comprehend deep truths through myths, legends and
universal ideas. Because music and movement are universal, even primordial, the
deep part of us that understands the arc of a story is particularly illuminated
by dance.
Every pirouette, every
carried lift [of Sir Kenneth MacMillan’s choreography of Prokofiev’s Romeo
and Juliet], has brought us to this moment where stillness reigns. It
is a beautiful example of how movement — and the spaces in between — resonate
with us on a deeply emotional level. Dance can convey fear, love or
joy, or even go deeper into the tormented tempest of the human condition.
Outline
I.
Introduction
II.
Principal Characteristics of Mytho-poeic
Thought
a. What
is myth?
b. Frankforts’
“Myth and Reality”
c. Cassirer’s
symbolic forms
d. The
Appeal of Stories
III.
The Age of Ideological Scenarios
IV.
Contemporary Mytho-poeic Political
Thinking
Select
Bibliography
Stories
and Story-telling
[1]
Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1946. The essay is hereinafter referred to as
“M&R.” For many years an abridged edition of the book was in print as a
Penguin paperback with the apt title Before Philosophy. Plato might have
entitled it Back Into the Cave.
[2]
The
1925 edition of Philosophie der symbolischen Formen II: Das mythische Denken
is cited. Hereinafter referred to as “PSF II.” Also cited are works by Paul
Radin and Rudolf Otto.
[3]
Ernst Cassirer, An Essay on Man (New Haven: Yale University Press,
1944), 74. (Hereinafter referred to as “EM.”)
[4]
M&R,
7. Cp. Cassirer, The Myth of the State (New Haven: Yale University
Press, 1946), hereinafter referred to “MS”: “It is true that in later times we
find myths made by individuals, as, for example, the famous Platonic myths. But
here one of the most essential features of the genuine myths is entirely
missing. Plato created them in an entirely free spirit; he was not under their
power, he directed them according to his own purposes: the purposes of
dialectical and ethical thought. Genuine myth does not possess this
philosophical freedom; for the images in which it lives are not known as
images. They are not regarded as symbols but as realities.” MS, 47.
[5]
Cited
by Cassirer in EM, 75.
[6]
EM,
73: “There is no natural phenomenon and no phenomenon of human life that is not
capable of a mythical interpretation, and which does not call for such an
interpretation.”
[7] “Myth and Reality,” 4. MS, 37: “[R]eligion and myth begin with the awareness of the universality and fundamental identity of life. . . . It is not necessary that this all-pervading life be conceived in a personal form (emphasis added).”
[8]
M&R, 4. Cassirer
refers to this as “consanguinity”: the view of life of the primitive mind “is a
synthetic, not an analytic one. Life is not divided into classes and
subclasses. It is felt as an unbroken continuous whole which does
not admit of any clean-cut and trenchant distinctions (emphasis added).” “The
consanguinity of all forms of life seems to be a general presupposition of
mythical thought.” EM, 81, 83.
[9]
M&R,
6. Politically, Müsil’s second reality
comes to mind. The Frankforts’ and Cassirer’s point here is that mythical
reality is not imposed or projected upon “true” reality: mythical reality is
the only reality available to primitive man.
[10] Ibid., 5-6. Mircea Eliade emphatically makes the same point in The Sacred and the Profane: The Nature of Religion (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and Company, 1959), Harper Torch Book edition, 16.
[11]
Ibid., 17. The experiences of the living things that
fill the world of ancient man are not necessarily hierophanies or theophanies.
Mircea Eliade argued that within the “profane” world in which ancient man
lived, parts of that living world—living parts of the world—would manifest
themselves to man as extraordinary, as sacred or divine. Rudolf Otto, whose
work was the inspiration for Eliade’s The Sacred and the Profane, also
focuses more on these experiences of the divine than on mythic experience.
[12] EM, 80.
[13]
M&R,
5.
[14] Ibid., 4.
[15] Ibid., 6. Cassirer: “Nature, in its empirical or scientific sense, may be defined as ‘the existence of things as far as it is determined by general laws.’ Such a ‘nature’ does not exist for myths. The world of myth is a dramatic world—a world of actions, of forces, of conflicting powers. In every phenomenon of nature it sees the collision of these powers. Mythical perception is always impregnated with these emotional qualities.” EM, 76. Emphasis added; footnote deleted.
[16] Ibid., 7.
[17] “Critical Idealism as a Philosophy of Culture,” in Symbol, Myth, and Culture, ed. Donald Phillip Verene (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1979), 64-91. Critical philosophy or idealist philosophy consciously focuses on how we know things, thus assuming that we do know things.
[18] See his “Introduction,” in his 1942 book The Logic of the Humanities (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1960, 1961)
[19] Cassirer seems to say that symbolic objectification is the or a distinctly human task: Explaining that symbolic expression “is the common denominator in all [man’s] cultural activities” such as myth, language, art, and religion, he continues, “These activities are widely different, but they fulfill one and the same task: the task of objectification.” MS, 45. Emphasis in original. See also his lecture “Language and Art II," in Symbol, Myth, and Culture: Essays and Lectures of Ernst Cassirer, 1935-1945, ed. Donald Phillip Verene (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1979), 166-175.
[20] He indicated that had he the time, the symbolic form of art would also have been included in the work. See the chapter on art in Essay on Man (1944) and the 1942 lectures on art and language in Symbol, Myth, and Culture.
[21] Cassirer, Language and Myth, trans. Suzanne K Langer (Garden City, NY: Dover Books edition, 1946), 88. Hereinafter referred to as L&M. Language and Myth was originally published in 1924, when Cassirer was working on volumes one and two of PSF. Accord: “Myth is an offspring of emotion[,] and its emotional background imbues all its productions with its own specific color.” EM, 82.
[22]
See generally his 1920s works Language and Myth and the three volumes of
The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, particularly volume two on Mythical
Thinking. In particular, L&M, chapters 3 and 6; PSF II, Pt. 1, chapter 1,
“The Mythical Consciousness of the Object.”
[23] L&M, 35. Among his studies of mythical thought, in addition to L&M are The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms: Mythical Thought, volume 2 of the three-, now four-, volume work on The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, first published in 1925; chapter 9 of An Essay on Man, published in 1944; and Part One of The Myth of the State, published in 1946. Chapter four of The Myth of the State is particularly relevant to the Frankforts’ essay, which appeared the same year. See note 2, supra. Cassirer, while not using the term “mytho-poeic in these texts frequently refers to “mythical thinking” and the “myth-making” function of the mind.
[24] L&M, 88.
[25] MS, 44. See also EM, 77, where Cassirer contrasts the fundamental, distinct physiognomic qualities of our experiences from the mere perceptual or sensory qualities. Consider the “outside in” approach to acting: act sad and morose and you will feel sad and morose.
[26] EM, 79: “Myth is not a system of dogmatic creeds. It consists much more in actions than in mere images and representations.” “That ritual is prior to dogma . . . seems now to be a generally adopted maxim.” “To study myths, we must first study rites.” MS, 24. Cp. PSF II, 38.
[27] MS, 284-285. [Sacramentality]
[28] MS, 46. “But if these rites are turned into myths a new element appears. Man is no longer satisfied with doing certain things—he raises the question of what these things ‘mean’.” The Frankforts’ comment that rituals are the acting out of myths thus puts the cart before the horse. See MS, 42.
[29] MS, 44-45: Cassirer refers to animals’ “instinctive emotions”—for example, fear of certain other animals or shapes. In animals, “The awareness of . . . different emotional qualities neither presupposes an act of reflection nor can it be accounted for by the individual experience of the animal.” We hear this popularly discussed as the “lizard brain” or the “flee or fight” reaction. Cassirer says that the difference between the animal and human response to such perceived emotional qualities is that man differentiates the emotions more specifically and expresses them symbolically instead of in simple, unstructured behavioral reactions.
[30] MS, 43.
[31] Ibid., 48.
[32] EM, 79, 80: Citing Durkheim: “Not nature but society is the true model of myth. All its fundamental motives are projections of man’s social life. By these projections, nature becomes the image of the social world,” not vice versa. “The fundamental social character of myth is uncontroverted.” Cp. Eric Voegelin, The New Science of Politics, ch. 2.
[33] MS, 47.
[34] EM, 77-78, 82.
[35] See note 23, supra. (MS, 44.) See also the short appended list of sources and summaries hurriedly gathered on the subject.
[36] “Captivate”: to make captive; “enthrall”: to enslave.
[37] Elena Renken, “How Stories Connect And Persuade Us: Unleashing The Brain Power Of Narrative,” npr.org (April 11, 2020)
[38] The NeuroLeadership Staff, “The Neuroscience of Storytelling,” The NeuroLeadership Institute (September 30, 2021).
[39] “Storytelling And The Brain: Understanding The Neuroscience Behind Our Love For Stories,” Power of Storytelling.com (February 7, 2023).
[40] Joshua VanDeBrake, “The Science of Storytelling: Why We Love Stories,” in The Startup and on <medium.com> (September 27, 2018). Cp. Paul Zak, “Why Your Brain Loves Good Storytelling,” Harvard Business Review (October 28, 2014): “This research was given a boost when, with funding from the U.S. Department of Defense, we developed ways to measure oxytocin release noninvasively at up to one thousand times per second.” ???
[41] Ibid. VanDebrake, note – supra: “You have likely heard that storytelling is important for business, marketing, and for life in general.” Zak: “These findings on the neurobiology of storytelling are relevant to business settings.”
[42] Calli McMurray, “Why the Brain Loves Stories,” BrainFacts.org (March 4, 2021). Reyhaneh Maktoufi is a Civic Science Fellow in misinformation at NOVA.
[43] Karl Popper, The Open Society and its Enemies, vol. 1, 4th ed. (New York: Harper and Row, 1962), 8. Under his concept of “historicism” (not Strauss’s “historicism”), Popper describes the central historicist doctrine as “the doctrine that history is controlled by specific historical or evolutionary laws whose discovery would enable us to prophesy the destiny of man.” Ibid., 8. Popper’s book, first published in 1944, focuses on Nazism and Communism as prime examples of historicism. Cassirer’s Myth of the State is also an analysis of 20th century totalitarianism, but only in the form of fascism and imperialism, not Marxism or communism.
[44] Gerhart Niemeyer, Between Nothingness and Paradise (Baton Rouge: LSU Press, 1971).
[45] See Hermann Rauschning’s The Revolution of Nihilism (New York: Longmans, Green and Co., 1939) for his argument that many higher-level Nazis were ready to discard the racial “myth” once it had exhausted its appeal and ability to motivate the masses for another myth to propel the “movement.” Similar stories abound about apparatchiks in the second half of the twentieth century, laboring in the party only for personal gain or power.
[46] See Part III of the book: “The Myth of the Twentieth Century.” Part II on the concept of the “state” comprises over 130 pages.
[47] Quotes from MS, 3, 280, 298.
[48] MS, 282. Cp. Kenneth Minogue’s claim that the central idea of “an ideological life” is “less a doctrine than a machine for generating doctrines.” “My argument, then, is an exploration of the hypothesis that there is a pure theory of ideology, and while from one point of view it is a critique, from another it is a do-it-yourself ideology kit (emphasis added).” Kenneth Minogue, Alien Powers: The Pure Theory of Ideology, 2d ed. (Wilmington: ISI Books, 2008), 2, 8.
[49] 279-280, 289.
[50] Cassirer’s short analysis of the transformation of language by totalitarian movements provides insights in such ideologies as underly the present political correctness and woke-ness movements. Cp., Minogue, Alien Powers.
[51] Compare Cassirer’s analysis to the different subsequent conceptualizations of ideological thought in, inter alia, Norman Cohn’s five characteristics of “millenarian salvation” in The Pursuit of the Millennium (1957, 1970); Eric Voegelin’s conception of “gnostic mass movements” in "Ersatz Religion," in Science, Politics and Gnosticism (1960); Richard H. Cox, Ideology, Politics, and Political Theory (1969); Gerhart Niemeyer’s “total critiques” in Between Nothingness and Paradise (1971); Frederick Watkins’s five distinctive characteristics of ideology in Kramnick and Watkins, The Age of Ideology: Political Thought, 1750 to the Present (1979); Roy Macridis’s definitions of ideology in Contemporary Political Ideologies (1980, 1983); Noel O'Sullivan’s four characteristics of the “activist style of politics” in Fascism (1983); and Kenneth Minogue, Alien Powers: The Pure Theory of Ideology (1985).
[52] See Graeme Wood, “What ISIS Really Wants,” The Atlantic, March, 2015; Richard J. Ellis, The Darkside of the Left, (Lawrence, KS: University of Kansas Press, 1998), chapter 9: “Apocalypse and Authoritarianism in the Radical Environmental Movement.”
[53] Minogue, note 47, supra, “Introduction to the Second Edition,” xxx-xxxi. Minogue’s Twentieth Century paradigm “myth” is Marxism, not Nazism.
[54]
EM,
77: “If we are under the strain of a violent emotion we have still this
dramatic conception of all things.” MS: “Even in primitive societies where myth
pervades and governs the whole of man’s social feeling and social life it is
not always operative in the same way nor does it always appear with the same
strength.”
[55] I recently reviewed the primary election brochures for five candidates for congress. The online brochures consisted of extended resumés and “vision statements.” Not one explained the candidate’s position on any particular issue!
[56] That period was also influenced in part by the millenarian scenario explained so well by Ernest Tuveson in Redeemer Nation: The Idea of America’s Millennial Role (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1968. You also may want to compare a recent newspaper article—“Campaigns Go Light on Policy Specifics,” in Wall Street Journal, August 24-25, 2024, A1—with the conclusion of Peggy Noonan’s weekly column in the same issue, A13, on the presidential campaign: “This is going to be all about policy”!
[57] Leviathan, chapter 5.
[58] MS, 298.